- 25 Jul 2012 15:47
#14015200
This post was written for another thread, but the subject deserves its own discussion.
Here is my position in general: Sometimes, it is better for the tree to bend, rather than break. I think that there are important exceptions, examples from history, which illustrate quite clearly that the unregulated self-interest of private parties does not always lead to the best result. In these cases, I believe that a responsible government should act, in the interest of a free market. If we strictly adhere to orthodox libertarianism in these cases, then the market actually becomes less free (more restricted).
Eran, for his part, is interested in understanding the difference between speech and commerce. All ideological differences aside, that would be a useful end.
No, no , no! Not everything can be boiled down to property rights! Falsely yelling fire is in a crowded theater is not illegal because it violates some rule of conduct stipulated by the theater's owner. It is illegal, because doing this can cause people to be hurt or killed. It would be just as illegal, I think, to cause a public panic on false pretexts in any enclosed area, whether it was privately owned, whether any "codes" had been stipulated by the owner or not. All of that is quite immaterial. Falsely yelling fire in a crowded theater endangers the people in the theater (the rights of the property owner are secondary).
Of course, it is. It is a reasonable limit that we all can agree on. It can be just as dangerous to falsely yell fire as it is to actually set a fire. The laws against arson limit my freedom to set fires where ever I choose, also. All such laws limit the freedom of the individual--or to be more precise, they set limits, and then the state imposes penalties on those who cross the line.
Like you, I am reluctant to impose any limitations on our citizenry, except those that are absolutely necessary. However, I think you will agree that some limitations are necessary. For example, the right to assembly only refers to public space, I think. You cannot just assemble a mob in some guy's house, if he doesn't want you there. Your right to assembly does not trump this guy's right to peace and privacy in his own domicile. You can stand on a public street, and as long as you offer no significant obstruction, you can hand out fliers, solicit signatures, donations, and preach whatever you want to whoever you want (or you should be able to). But you can't necessarily do this in some guy's tavern or theater, without his consent. In some cases, property rights do trump individual freedoms, like the right to free speech.
There are further limitations on speech that are quite reasonable. Your right to free speech protects your right to lie, to a certain extent, but there are penalties for slander and libel, and there should be. Plagiarism is another limitation, although this last example has less to do with speech rights, and more to do with business practices (you cannot profit from intellectual material that you fraudulently claim as your own).
Not at all. But, there are reasonable limitations that we can impose. I have outlined some of these above. It is my belief that society is complex, and there will always be conflicts between the rights of one individual against another, one business against another, one class against another, and so on. As an orderly society, we must resolve these conflicts on a case by case basis. We must be careful, because in all cases, the rights of one party will have have to be affirmed, and the rights of another party will be negated. There is no way to dodge responsibility here. In order to affirm one thing, you have negate another.
Thankfully, there are general rules of thumb that can be helpful when deliberating over these conflicts. In cases of speech, that rule of thumb is the first amendment. It is not absolute, but it holds good 99 times out of a 100. In cases involving property and commerce, I am willing to admit that libertarian principles can provide a good rule of thumb. But there are important exceptions, and orthodox libertarians seem completely blind to these exceptions.
You are trying to resolve the conflict by pretending that there is no conflict. I agree, a proprietor has a right to refuse his services to anyone, based on nothing more than his own personal whims. And, the guy with money has a right to exchange that money for goods on the free market. The money is useless to him unless he can exchange it for goods, otherwise it has no value. There is a conflict here, even if you would like to assert otherwise.
Say our buyer lives in a sparsely populated area, and he needs some item from the local store, but the racist proprietor refuses to sell to him, and now he must spend all kinds of money and time to go to a store in the next county. Basically, the proprietor enforces a kind of miniature inflation on the seller. An item that once cost $1 now costs $2, because he must shell out for gas, take an hour off of work, or whatever. To hell with that! He is an American citizen, by God. And it says right on the bill: "Good for all debts public and private." This is legal tender, backed by the central bank of the federal government. If our proprietor takes this currency from one person, he is participating in the system, so he should have to take the money from everyone. That is how the system works: consistency. When you back the right of the seller to discriminate, you implicitly attack, not just the rights of the buyer, you also attack the value of his money--you attack the whole idea of money.
And the buyer shouldn't have to cringe and scrounge for a bag of groceries to feed his family, when he has legal money to spend; he shouldn't have to beg someone else to buy his groceries, like a little kid hanging around outside the Quickemart, trying to get booze. Not as an adult citizen of a free republic! We should trample on this man's rights, make him servile and dependent, and impede the flow of commerce, just to satisfy the racist whims of some redneck proprietor? No right is absolute.
Do you think that the negro, frozen out of the local market by the discrimination of racist proprietors, makes a voluntary decision to expend time and money to purchase his goods from a distant market? These cases will be rare--maybe not so rare in 1964, but definitely rare in 2012. These cases may be exceptional, but no matter how rare, they potentially constitute an exceptional imposition on the buyer (no one should have to go thirty miles, just to purchase a commodity that the buyer could get one mile away, if it wasn't for some racist local proprietor). On the other hand, the imposition made on independent proprietors by title II of the Civil Rights Act is relatively minor. That's why I am willing to support title II. It is a trade off--one party's rights must be affirmed, another's rights must be denied. If you affirm the rights of the buyer, you save him potentially major costs and inconvenience, but you have to deny the rights of the seller. However, title II imposes no extra costs on the proprietor, and it causes him only minor inconvenience.
Wrong. It is more akin to my example above, of the guy handed out pamphlets on a public street. Remember the critical exception: if he is not an obstruction. For example, you are not allowed to set up shop directly in front of the entrance to some business. He is allowed to get his message out there, but he is not allowed to impede the flow of business into and out of this local shop. There will be local ordinances that dictate how far away he must be from the entrance of a business, and there should be. These ordinances are a minor imposition on the street agitator--he will be able to set up shop a few feet down the road, in a spot that is just as public. He just can't be an obstruction. For the shopkeeper, however, if some agitator is allowed to set up directly in front of this other guy's shop, harassing all of his customers, this can be a major imposition.
This is another general rule of thumb, I think. In cases where there is a conflict between the rights of two parties, you should tend to support the rights of the party who are most imposed on in the conflict, versus those that are least imposed on. It is a minor imposition to force a proprietor to sell his wares to all legitimate buyers, regardless of race. But the discrimination of one single proprietor, well positioned in the local market, can cause a major imposition on many of his buyers.
Similarly, it is a minor imposition to ask me not to cause a dangerous commotion in a public enclosure, not to start a fire where ever I feel like, not to a assemble a mob on private property without permission, not to start preaching and agitating in a public business absent the owner's consent, and so on. These are small and reasonable limitations on my freedom. I will trade these off, in order to live in an orderly and democratic society.
Here is my position in general: Sometimes, it is better for the tree to bend, rather than break. I think that there are important exceptions, examples from history, which illustrate quite clearly that the unregulated self-interest of private parties does not always lead to the best result. In these cases, I believe that a responsible government should act, in the interest of a free market. If we strictly adhere to orthodox libertarianism in these cases, then the market actually becomes less free (more restricted).
Eran, for his part, is interested in understanding the difference between speech and commerce. All ideological differences aside, that would be a useful end.
Eran wrote:Public theaters actually have owners, and those owners are perfectly within their rights to stipulate rules of conduct under which people may attend performances. One of those rules prohibits unnecessarily disrupting performances.
No, no , no! Not everything can be boiled down to property rights! Falsely yelling fire is in a crowded theater is not illegal because it violates some rule of conduct stipulated by the theater's owner. It is illegal, because doing this can cause people to be hurt or killed. It would be just as illegal, I think, to cause a public panic on false pretexts in any enclosed area, whether it was privately owned, whether any "codes" had been stipulated by the owner or not. All of that is quite immaterial. Falsely yelling fire in a crowded theater endangers the people in the theater (the rights of the property owner are secondary).
Eran wrote:This often-cited example is not (or need not be) a limit on free speech.
Of course, it is. It is a reasonable limit that we all can agree on. It can be just as dangerous to falsely yell fire as it is to actually set a fire. The laws against arson limit my freedom to set fires where ever I choose, also. All such laws limit the freedom of the individual--or to be more precise, they set limits, and then the state imposes penalties on those who cross the line.
Like you, I am reluctant to impose any limitations on our citizenry, except those that are absolutely necessary. However, I think you will agree that some limitations are necessary. For example, the right to assembly only refers to public space, I think. You cannot just assemble a mob in some guy's house, if he doesn't want you there. Your right to assembly does not trump this guy's right to peace and privacy in his own domicile. You can stand on a public street, and as long as you offer no significant obstruction, you can hand out fliers, solicit signatures, donations, and preach whatever you want to whoever you want (or you should be able to). But you can't necessarily do this in some guy's tavern or theater, without his consent. In some cases, property rights do trump individual freedoms, like the right to free speech.
There are further limitations on speech that are quite reasonable. Your right to free speech protects your right to lie, to a certain extent, but there are penalties for slander and libel, and there should be. Plagiarism is another limitation, although this last example has less to do with speech rights, and more to do with business practices (you cannot profit from intellectual material that you fraudulently claim as your own).
...do you support European-style prohibition on certain types of expression?
Not at all. But, there are reasonable limitations that we can impose. I have outlined some of these above. It is my belief that society is complex, and there will always be conflicts between the rights of one individual against another, one business against another, one class against another, and so on. As an orderly society, we must resolve these conflicts on a case by case basis. We must be careful, because in all cases, the rights of one party will have have to be affirmed, and the rights of another party will be negated. There is no way to dodge responsibility here. In order to affirm one thing, you have negate another.
Thankfully, there are general rules of thumb that can be helpful when deliberating over these conflicts. In cases of speech, that rule of thumb is the first amendment. It is not absolute, but it holds good 99 times out of a 100. In cases involving property and commerce, I am willing to admit that libertarian principles can provide a good rule of thumb. But there are important exceptions, and orthodox libertarians seem completely blind to these exceptions.
Each party has a right to control its own property. Prior to the transaction, the buyer owns his money, the seller owns some merchandise. Neither party has a right to force the other to transact. Rather, a transaction takes place when both sides agree. Absent agreement from either side, the transaction doesn't take place.
You are trying to resolve the conflict by pretending that there is no conflict. I agree, a proprietor has a right to refuse his services to anyone, based on nothing more than his own personal whims. And, the guy with money has a right to exchange that money for goods on the free market. The money is useless to him unless he can exchange it for goods, otherwise it has no value. There is a conflict here, even if you would like to assert otherwise.
Say our buyer lives in a sparsely populated area, and he needs some item from the local store, but the racist proprietor refuses to sell to him, and now he must spend all kinds of money and time to go to a store in the next county. Basically, the proprietor enforces a kind of miniature inflation on the seller. An item that once cost $1 now costs $2, because he must shell out for gas, take an hour off of work, or whatever. To hell with that! He is an American citizen, by God. And it says right on the bill: "Good for all debts public and private." This is legal tender, backed by the central bank of the federal government. If our proprietor takes this currency from one person, he is participating in the system, so he should have to take the money from everyone. That is how the system works: consistency. When you back the right of the seller to discriminate, you implicitly attack, not just the rights of the buyer, you also attack the value of his money--you attack the whole idea of money.
And the buyer shouldn't have to cringe and scrounge for a bag of groceries to feed his family, when he has legal money to spend; he shouldn't have to beg someone else to buy his groceries, like a little kid hanging around outside the Quickemart, trying to get booze. Not as an adult citizen of a free republic! We should trample on this man's rights, make him servile and dependent, and impede the flow of commerce, just to satisfy the racist whims of some redneck proprietor? No right is absolute.
I believe there should be no limits on voluntary market transactions. By forcing a restaurant owner to serve people he doesn't wish to serve, the transaction is no longer voluntary. In effect, the state is assuming partial control over the restaurant.
Do you think that the negro, frozen out of the local market by the discrimination of racist proprietors, makes a voluntary decision to expend time and money to purchase his goods from a distant market? These cases will be rare--maybe not so rare in 1964, but definitely rare in 2012. These cases may be exceptional, but no matter how rare, they potentially constitute an exceptional imposition on the buyer (no one should have to go thirty miles, just to purchase a commodity that the buyer could get one mile away, if it wasn't for some racist local proprietor). On the other hand, the imposition made on independent proprietors by title II of the Civil Rights Act is relatively minor. That's why I am willing to support title II. It is a trade off--one party's rights must be affirmed, another's rights must be denied. If you affirm the rights of the buyer, you save him potentially major costs and inconvenience, but you have to deny the rights of the seller. However, title II imposes no extra costs on the proprietor, and it causes him only minor inconvenience.
Outlawing discrimination by private parties enjoys no similar line of reasoning. It is much more akin to outlawing racist speech.
Wrong. It is more akin to my example above, of the guy handed out pamphlets on a public street. Remember the critical exception: if he is not an obstruction. For example, you are not allowed to set up shop directly in front of the entrance to some business. He is allowed to get his message out there, but he is not allowed to impede the flow of business into and out of this local shop. There will be local ordinances that dictate how far away he must be from the entrance of a business, and there should be. These ordinances are a minor imposition on the street agitator--he will be able to set up shop a few feet down the road, in a spot that is just as public. He just can't be an obstruction. For the shopkeeper, however, if some agitator is allowed to set up directly in front of this other guy's shop, harassing all of his customers, this can be a major imposition.
This is another general rule of thumb, I think. In cases where there is a conflict between the rights of two parties, you should tend to support the rights of the party who are most imposed on in the conflict, versus those that are least imposed on. It is a minor imposition to force a proprietor to sell his wares to all legitimate buyers, regardless of race. But the discrimination of one single proprietor, well positioned in the local market, can cause a major imposition on many of his buyers.
Similarly, it is a minor imposition to ask me not to cause a dangerous commotion in a public enclosure, not to start a fire where ever I feel like, not to a assemble a mob on private property without permission, not to start preaching and agitating in a public business absent the owner's consent, and so on. These are small and reasonable limitations on my freedom. I will trade these off, in order to live in an orderly and democratic society.